books book reviews

philosophy and science books

reviewed by T. J. Nelson

Score+4

Information and the Nature of Reality: From Physics to Metaphysics
by Paul Davies and Niels Henrik Gregersen, eds. Cambridge, 2014, 487 pages

F rom the exciting title, you might think that someone has finally figured out that the universe is composed not of matter and energy, but of information. Almost. What we have is a group of philosophers, physicists, biologists, and theologians speculating about information theory, quantum mechanics, and God.

The true experts at this symposium, which was held in Copenhagen, are the theologians, who are flexing their muscles with this so-called “new physics” as a new take on the nature of God, albeit a pantheistic one.

This new physics is explained in the chapter by Henry P. Stapp. As every schoolchild knows (if they were paying attention in particle physics class), quantum mechanics says that the smallest phenomena of nature—photons and elementary particles—behave probabilistically, not deterministically. For example, there is no way to predict when an individual radioactive atom will decay. A photon is merely a wave function until it is ‘observed.’ Observing it causes the wave to interact with matter at a fixed place in a process called decoherence.

Many physicists would say this just means we don’t quite understand how things work at a fundamental level. The term ‘observed’ really means ‘interacted with its target’ and this whole business about an observer being necessary is just an linguistic artifact. Better to speak in the language of mathematics and avoid creating confusion.

But what if it's not just an artifact? Could quantum states be literally maintained in the brain? Penrose and others thought so, and took the term ‘observation’ to mean a requirement for an ‘observer.’ Penrose speculated that the conscious moment is the moment of quantum decoherence.

For technical reasons, Stapp added the ‘quantum Zeno effect’ whereby observing a particle prevents it from decaying (which is a quantum mechanical process). He says that the universe itself requires an observer in order to be real: “Without these acts [of the brain] there is nothing but a continuous smear of meaningless un-actualized possibilities.” This means there must have been an original Observer:

“This situation is concordant with the idea of a powerful God that creates the universe and its laws to get things started, but then bequeaths part of this power to beings created in his own image, at least with regard to their power to make physically efficacious decisions on the basis of reasons and evaluations.”

I don't want to be a party-pooper, but it must be said that this view is not shared by all scientists. The existence of a quantum Zeno effect has been disputed, and most think quantum phenomena are too small to exist in a large item like a brain cell, let alone the whole brain.

But strange ideas can evolve into powerful new theories. It pays to remember that this is not a textbook, and none of this is meant to be a final word on the subject; it is really just a bunch of scientists and theologians brainstorming and having fun with radical new ideas.

The theologians and philosophers eat it up like manna from heaven. Philosophers like the idea of indeterminacy because it gives them a weapon to use against reductionism and the materialist worldview. Theologians love the idea of consciousness creating the universe. Theologian Philip Clayton talks about ‘post-materialist theory.’ He quotes d’Espagnat, who said in In Search of Reality that we cannot say reality is “just this way or that,” since our perception creates reality. If any postmodernists had been present, they probably would have liked it even more.

Shannon entropy and DNA information, which are widely accepted, are also nicely discussed. The chief editor, physicist Paul Davies, introduces the topic of information. There are 10122 bits of information in the universe, he says, and therefore the laws of physics have an intrinsically finite accuracy. Seth Lloyd takes it a step further by proposing that the universe is a giant quantum computer. However, we know that qubits contain infinite amounts of information, and therefore any universe with a qubit contains unlimited amounts of information. So there seems to be some room for debate there, but whether it’s 10122 or infinity, it’s a lot.

Believe it or not, the biologists are the most skeptical. Perhaps justifiably so; the idea that the brain is a quantum computer conflicts with what we know about chemistry and neuroanatomy. The biologists are more interested in the information encoded in DNA. They discuss the semiotic interactions among ants, altruism, and the language of genes. “The processes of life would implode into a jumble of chaos,” writes Bernd-Olaf Küppers, “if they were not perpetually stabilized by information and communication.” The concept of intelligent design is discussed and critiqued at length, but not by the biologists—by the theologians.

What this says about the symposium is that there must have been a remarkably vigorous exchange of ideas, many coming from unexpected sources. The writing is non-technical and clear. Readers interested in how science works will find it fascinating. Religious readers may even find it inspiring. Believing in a conscious universe may require a leap of faith, but whether one accepts it or not, no one can dispute it's a challenging and provocative idea. I almost wish I'd been there.

jan 20, 2015; revised jan 21, 2015

Score+4

Paradoxes and Inconsistent Mathematics
by Zach Weber
Cambridge, 2021, 325 pages

P aradoxes, says Zach Weber, are deductions that end in contra­dictions. The classic example is the liar paradox (“This sentence is false.”) Another example is the so-called sorites paradox:

If the top of a mountain is ‘high’ and the foot of the mountain is ‘low’, at which point does it stop being ‘low’ and start being ‘high’? If there is such a point on the ‘low’ side, the next point infinitesimally close to it is ‘high’ even though its elevation is almost exactly the same.

There are many others: Curry's Paradox, Gričin's paradox, and the famous Russell's paradox, which created a ‘crisis in the found­ations of mathe­matics’ by finding antinomies in set theory and overturned a large body of Cantor's work. The crisis was considered so serious that the great mathematician David Hilbert demanded a solution be found to restore “the honor of the human under­standing itself.”

In this book, Zach Weber rises to the challenge. He proposes a variation of classical logic called dialetheic para­consis­tency. Dialetheic means that some contra­dictions are true. Paracon­sistency rejects the idea that if even one contra­diction can be true, then anything goes—everything becomes true (which is bad).

This adds to the growing list of systems of non-classical logic as described by Graham Priest. The challenge has always been that they're hard to use. They create inconsistencies and sometimes ‘explode’ into what's called ex contradictione quodlibet where everything comes out ‘true’, so the second half of the book is devoted to detailed proofs showing this doesn't happen. Many readers will find their eyes glazing over in this section.

I'm no math­ema­tician, but it seems to me that many of the paradoxes (especially sorites) are not really paradoxes, but artifacts of language. Surely math­ema­tic­ians couldn't be confused about whether a point on a mountain is ‘high’ or ‘low’, nor is anyone really baffled that the Great Red Spot on Jupiter doesn't have an infinitely sharp boundary. These are just words.

Take Russell's paradox, concerning a set of all sets that do not contain themselves as members. It seems to me that if you can empirically demonstrate that such a set exists, you have a paradox. If not, maybe all you have is a word game expressed in math. Changing the rules of logic to make paradoxes go away seems like an airline pilot trying to regain altitude by redefining ‘down’ to be ‘up’.

For a while it's not clear that Weber's strategy will really be as radical as that. Maybe just changing the definition of an invalid argument from ‘false’ to ‘untrue’ would be enough:

Since ⊤ is so fundamental, then, in making any sense of the world, this would be a good reason to take ⊤ and ⊥ to be part of the logical vocabulary, part of deductive logic itself . . . it's taking the rejection of absurdity—absolute consistency, nontriviality—as the starting point for the organon of logic itself. Call it an appeal to the principle of sufficient reason, Premise 0, an appeal to the very possibility of reason itself. [p.293]

But he ultimately concludes that paradoxes, by which he means things that are both true and false, are a normal part of the universe. Contradictions can be true, so they suddenly are no longer paradoxical:

Why are there paradoxes? There are no paradoxes. [p.288]

You are in the city and walking out of it. At some point, you are in the city; at some point, you are not. . . . There are paradoxes everywhere. [p.299]

Wait a minute. If paradoxes are not paradoxes, isn't that itself a paradox? Could this be another case of “revenge” he talks about, where addressing a paradox causes it to pop up even stronger somewhere else? It no longer matters. He becomes almost giddy with the prospect of banishing the problem of paradoxes forever by including them into the rules of logic itself:

Paradoxes are found at the boundary points of objects. But every point is the boundary of some object. Paradoxes are ordinary.

So, what should we make of the 20th century crisis in the foundations of mathematics? Was it much ado over nothing? I guess your answer would depend on whether logic is something that's built into nature or a set of rules we can change at will.

feb 12 2022. updated feb 13 2022